Jacques Hyman's book does a good job in refuting the claims of nuclear determinists. Hyman argues that weak state institutions, more than anything else, prevent
states from attaining nuclear weapons. He believes that questions over the
ability of a state to successfully develop, maintain, and complete a nuclear
program cannot be answered through purely technical reasoning, but must include
political analysis of state institutions.
Hyman makes his argument by
analyzing the relationship between politicians and scientists at both the micro
and macro level. At the micro level, he argues the professionalism of the
scientific corps tasked with undertaking a nuclear program is paramount to the
program’s efficient completion. Achieving a high level of professionalism rests
on politicians granting scientists autonomy. Autonomy is attained by providing
scientists with the resources they need, by allowing them to control their own
work schedules, and by convincing – not coercing – them to buy into the nuclear
project. Hyman notes that it is hard for a state to foster a feeling of
professionalism among scientists, especially in states lacking strong
institutions.
In linking the micro level to the
macro, Hyman argues the reason why some states stifle scientific autonomy and
professionalism and others do not is based on differing degrees of
institutional constraint placed on the actions of the top leadership of the
state. Hyman places all states into two organizational groups: Weberian
legal-rational and neo-patrimonial.
Weberian legal-rational states have strong institutions that prevent the
state’s leadership from interfering in the affairs of nuclear scientists, thus
granting them the autonomy and professionalism needed to carry out a
proliferation program. Neo-patrimonial states, however, lack strong
institutions that can block elites from meddling in the affairs of their
scientists. If these elites do meddle, then scientists will lose their autonomy
and professionalism and the completion of a nuclear program will become a
herculean task. As Hyman suggests, the reason why recent successful
proliferation programs have taken longer to complete as compared to the
programs carried out by the US and USSR in the early Cold War, is due to the
fact that most states currently working on nuclear weapons projects fall into
the neo-patrimonial category. So, Hyman gives us a good argument as to why nuclear determinism is wrong, now what does he say we should do about it?
The worst thing we can do, Hyman notes, is use military means to eliminate enemy proliferation programs. As he notes, military actions against enemy nuclear facilities and scientists often lead to the exact opposite of what they were intended to do. For instance, Hyman argues that the targeted assassinations of Iranian nuclear scientists by the US and Israel only convinces Iranian “scientific and technical workers to give their all to their country’s bomb project,” increasing the likelihood of the program’s success. Moreover, the almost blind faith accorded to this policy prescription demonstrates what has become an endemic failure of the US government to think at the strategic level. Complex questions, such as those surrounding how best to stop nuclear proliferation, require complex answers and strategic forethought. Framing these questions only in terms of technological capabilities limits the ability of the US to respond through means other than a military strike. In essence, we fail to see the forest from the trees. Instead, Hyman argues we should expand debate on these issues from the purely technical to the political to allow policymakers to view nuclear proliferation in a new light, creating opportunities for the development of new polices to combat a real problem in international relations. Herein lies the real benefit of Hymans book, for far more important than answering the question as to why some states are more successful than others at achieving their nuclear ambitions is Hyman’s call for us to break with our preconceived notions of nuclear weapons and view them from a higher, more objective plane. The challenge has been issued, can we meet it?
The worst thing we can do, Hyman notes, is use military means to eliminate enemy proliferation programs. As he notes, military actions against enemy nuclear facilities and scientists often lead to the exact opposite of what they were intended to do. For instance, Hyman argues that the targeted assassinations of Iranian nuclear scientists by the US and Israel only convinces Iranian “scientific and technical workers to give their all to their country’s bomb project,” increasing the likelihood of the program’s success. Moreover, the almost blind faith accorded to this policy prescription demonstrates what has become an endemic failure of the US government to think at the strategic level. Complex questions, such as those surrounding how best to stop nuclear proliferation, require complex answers and strategic forethought. Framing these questions only in terms of technological capabilities limits the ability of the US to respond through means other than a military strike. In essence, we fail to see the forest from the trees. Instead, Hyman argues we should expand debate on these issues from the purely technical to the political to allow policymakers to view nuclear proliferation in a new light, creating opportunities for the development of new polices to combat a real problem in international relations. Herein lies the real benefit of Hymans book, for far more important than answering the question as to why some states are more successful than others at achieving their nuclear ambitions is Hyman’s call for us to break with our preconceived notions of nuclear weapons and view them from a higher, more objective plane. The challenge has been issued, can we meet it?
No comments:
Post a Comment